Results for 'William J. Griffith'

1000+ found
Order:
  1.  11
    Sustaining attention in affective contexts during adolescence: age-related differences and association with elevated symptoms of depression and anxiety.D. L. Dunning, J. Parker, K. Griffiths, M. Bennett, A. Archer-Boyd, A. Bevan, S. Ahmed, C. Griffin, L. Foulkes, J. Leung, A. Sakhardande, T. Manly, W. Kuyken, J. M. G. Williams, S. -J. Blakemore & T. Dalgleish - forthcoming - Cognition and Emotion.
    Sustained attention, a key cognitive skill that improves during childhood and adolescence, tends to be worse in some emotional and behavioural disorders. Sustained attention is typically studied in non-affective task contexts; here, we used a novel task to index performance in affective versus neutral contexts across adolescence (N = 465; ages 11–18). We asked whether: (i) performance would be worse in negative versus neutral task contexts; (ii) performance would improve with age; (iii) affective interference would be greater in younger adolescents; (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  6
    Joan Stambaugh, "Nietzsche's Thought of Eternal Return". [REVIEW]William J. Griffith - 1975 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 13 (4):536.
  3. Religious Diversity.Paul J. Griffiths - 1988 - The Thomist 52 (2):319-327.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:REVIEW SYMPOSIUM 319 secular communities before making up their minds. But, in this case at least, minding theological business requires minding philosophical business. I wish all teachers of the Catholic community would study this book. JAMES J. BUCKLEY Loyola Oollege, Baltimore, Maryland RELIGIOUS DIVERSITY WILLIAM CHRISTIAN'S important new book appears at an opportune moment. It breaks new theoretical ground in the cross-cultural study of religious communities and religious (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4. New books. [REVIEW]Patrick Gardiner, C. C. W. Taylor, Leslie M. S. Griffiths, C. J. F. Williams, Richard Campbell, Brian Barry & J. C. Gosling - 1968 - Mind 77 (308):602-620.
    No categories
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5.  39
    A Mithraic Papyrus William M. Brashear: A Mithraic Catechism from Egypt. P. Berol. 21196 (Tyche Supplementband, I.) Pp. 70; 2 plates. Vienna: Holzhausen, 1992. Paper. [REVIEW]J. Gwyn Griffiths - 1994 - The Classical Review 44 (01):181-182.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6.  51
    Book Review Section 1. [REVIEW]Sylvester Kohut Jr, Nicholas C. Polos, Lois M. R. Louden, Cyril E. Griffith, Beverly Lindsay, Don T. Martin, M. M. Chambers, Joseph W. Newman, Harvey Neufeldt, Elizabeth Ihle, David C. Williams, James E. Christensen & J. Theodore Klein - 1978 - Educational Studies 9 (3):307-328.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7.  16
    Hannah Gay and William P. Griffith, The Chemistry Department at Imperial College: A History, 1845–2000. London: World Scientific Publishing, 2017. Pp. xi + 569 + illus. ISBN 978-1-78326-973-0. £56.00. [REVIEW]Peter J. T. Morris - 2018 - British Journal for the History of Science 51 (2):309-311.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  6
    Nietzsche’s Speech of Indirection.William J. Zanardi - 1984 - International Studies in Philosophy 16 (2):53-56.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9.  10
    Nietzsche’s Speech of Indirection.William J. Zanardi - 1984 - International Studies in Philosophy 16 (2):53-56.
  10. Syntactic semantics: Foundations of computational natural language understanding.William J. Rapaport - 1988 - In James H. Fetzer (ed.), Aspects of AI. D.
    This essay considers what it means to understand natural language and whether a computer running an artificial-intelligence program designed to understand natural language does in fact do so. It is argued that a certain kind of semantics is needed to understand natural language, that this kind of semantics is mere symbol manipulation (i.e., syntax), and that, hence, it is available to AI systems. Recent arguments by Searle and Dretske to the effect that computers cannot understand natural language are discussed, and (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  11. Understanding understanding: Syntactic semantics and computational cognition.William J. Rapaport - 1995 - Philosophical Perspectives 9:49-88.
    John Searle once said: "The Chinese room shows what we knew all along: syntax by itself is not sufficient for semantics. (Does anyone actually deny this point, I mean straight out? Is anyone actually willing to say, straight out, that they think that syntax, in the sense of formal symbols, is really the same as semantic content, in the sense of meanings, thought contents, understanding, etc.?)." I say: "Yes". Stuart C. Shapiro has said: "Does that make any sense? Yes: Everything (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  12. Holism, conceptual-role semantics, and syntactic semantics.William J. Rapaport - 2002 - Minds and Machines 12 (1):3-59.
    This essay continues my investigation of `syntactic semantics': the theory that, pace Searle's Chinese-Room Argument, syntax does suffice for semantics (in particular, for the semantics needed for a computational cognitive theory of natural-language understanding). Here, I argue that syntactic semantics (which is internal and first-person) is what has been called a conceptual-role semantics: The meaning of any expression is the role that it plays in the complete system of expressions. Such a `narrow', conceptual-role semantics is the appropriate sort of semantics (...)
    Direct download (11 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  13. How to pass a Turing test: Syntactic semantics, natural-language understanding, and first-person cognition.William J. Rapaport - 2000 - Journal of Logic, Language, and Information 9 (4):467-490.
    I advocate a theory of syntactic semantics as a way of understanding how computers can think (and how the Chinese-Room-Argument objection to the Turing Test can be overcome): (1) Semantics, considered as the study of relations between symbols and meanings, can be turned into syntax – a study of relations among symbols (including meanings) – and hence syntax (i.e., symbol manipulation) can suffice for the semantical enterprise (contra Searle). (2) Semantics, considered as the process of understanding one domain (by modeling (...)
    Direct download (12 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  14. How minds can be computational systems.William J. Rapaport - 1998 - Journal of Experimental and Theoretical Artificial Intelligence 10 (4):403-419.
    The proper treatment of computationalism, as the thesis that cognition is computable, is presented and defended. Some arguments of James H. Fetzer against computationalism are examined and found wanting, and his positive theory of minds as semiotic systems is shown to be consistent with computationalism. An objection is raised to an argument of Selmer Bringsjord against one strand of computationalism, namely, that Turing-Test± passing artifacts are persons, it is argued that, whether or not this objection holds, such artifacts will inevitably (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  15. What did you mean by that? Misunderstanding, negotiation, and syntactic semantics.William J. Rapaport - 2003 - Minds and Machines 13 (3):397-427.
    Syntactic semantics is a holistic, conceptual-role-semantic theory of how computers can think. But Fodor and Lepore have mounted a sustained attack on holistic semantic theories. However, their major problem with holism (that, if holism is true, then no two people can understand each other) can be fixed by means of negotiating meanings. Syntactic semantics and Fodor and Lepore’s objections to holism are outlined; the nature of communication, miscommunication, and negotiation is discussed; Bruner’s ideas about the negotiation of meaning are explored; (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  16. Philosophy of Computer Science.William J. Rapaport - 2005 - Teaching Philosophy 28 (4):319-341.
    There are many branches of philosophy called “the philosophy of X,” where X = disciplines ranging from history to physics. The philosophy of artificial intelligence has a long history, and there are many courses and texts with that title. Surprisingly, the philosophy of computer science is not nearly as well-developed. This article proposes topics that might constitute the philosophy of computer science and describes a course covering those topics, along with suggested readings and assignments.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  17. Meinongian theories and a Russellian paradox.William J. Rapaport - 1978 - Noûs 12 (2):153-180.
    This essay re-examines Meinong's "Über Gegenstandstheorie" and undertakes a clarification and revision of it that is faithful to Meinong, overcomes the various objections to his theory, and is capable of offering solutions to various problems in philosophy of mind and philosophy of language. I then turn to a discussion of a historically and technically interesting Russell-style paradox (now known as "Clark's Paradox") that arises in the modified theory. I also examine the alternative Meinong-inspired theories of Hector-Neri Castañeda and Terence Parsons.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   96 citations  
  18. An adverbial meinongian theory.William J. Rapaport - 1979 - Analysis 39 (March):75-81.
    A fundamental assumption of Alexius Meinong's 1904 Theory of Objects is the act-content-object analysis of psychological experiences. I suggest that Meinong's theory need not be based on this analysis, but that an adverbial theory might suffice. I then defend the adverbial alternative against an objection raised by Roderick Chisholm, and conclude by presenting an apparently more serious objection based on a paradox discovered by Romane Clark.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  19. Non-Existent Objects and Epistemological Ontology.William J. Rapaport - 1985 - Grazer Philosophische Studien 25 (1):61-95.
    This essay examines the role of non-existent objects in "epistemological ontology" — the study of the entities that make thinking possible. An earlier revision of Meinong's Theory of Objects is reviewed, Meinong's notions of Quasisein and Außersein are discussed, and a theory of Meinongian objects as "combinatorially possible" entities is presented.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  20. Critical Review of Minds, Brains and Science.William J. Rapaport - 1988 - Noûs 22 (4):585-609.
    Critical Review of Searle's Minds, Brains and Science.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  21. To think or not to think.William J. Rapaport - 1988 - Noûs 22 (4):585-609.
    A critical study of John Searle's Minds, Brains and Science (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1984).
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  22.  5
    The logic of truth: St. Thomas Aquinas's epistemology and Antonio Livi's alethic logic.William J. Slattery - 2015 - Roma, Italy: Casa editrice Leonardo da Vinci.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23.  1
    Order.William J. Sullivan - 2010 - In Piotr Stalmaszczyk (ed.), Philosophy of Language and Linguistics: Volume I: The Formal Turn; Volume II: The Philosophical Turn. De Gruyter. pp. 315-328.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24. Because mere calculating isn't thinking: Comments on Hauser's Why Isn't My Pocket Calculator a Thinking Thing?.William J. Rapaport - 1993 - Minds and Machines 3 (1):11-20.
    Hauser argues that his pocket calculator (Cal) has certain arithmetical abilities: it seems Cal calculates. That calculating is thinking seems equally untendentious. Yet these two claims together provide premises for a seemingly valid syllogism whose conclusion - Cal thinks - most would deny. He considers several ways to avoid this conclusion, and finds them mostly wanting. Either we ourselves can't be said to think or calculate if our calculation-like performances are judged by the standards proposed to rule out Cal; or (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  25.  17
    The Open and Closed Mind: Investigations into the Nature of Belief Systems and Personality Systems.William J. MacKinnon - 1961 - Philosophy of Science 28 (3):324-327.
  26.  75
    How could a “blind” evolutionary process have made human moral beliefs sensitive to strongly universal, objective moral standards?William J. Talbott - 2015 - Biology and Philosophy 30 (5):691-708.
    The evolutionist challenge to moral realism is the skeptical challenge that, if evolution is true, it would only be by chance, a “happy coincidence” as Sharon Street puts it, if human moral beliefs were true. The author formulates Street’s “happy coincidence” argument more precisely using a distinction between probabilistic sensitivity and insensitivity introduced by Elliott Sober. The author then considers whether it could be rational for us to believe that human moral judgments about particular cases are probabilistically sensitive to strongly (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  27. Meinongian Semantics and Artificial Intelligence.William J. Rapaport - 2013 - Humana Mente 6 (25):25-52.
    This essay describes computational semantic networks for a philosophical audience and surveys several approaches to semantic-network semantics. In particular, propositional semantic networks are discussed; it is argued that only a fully intensional, Meinongian semantics is appropriate for them; and several Meinongian systems are presented.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  28. Meinong, Defective Objects, and (Psycho-)Logical Paradox.William J. Rapaport - 1982 - Grazer Philosophische Studien 18 (1):17-39.
    Alexius Meinong developed a notion of defective objects in order to account for various logical and psychological paradoxes. The notion is of historical interest, since it presages recent work on the logical paradoxes by Herzberger and Kripke. But it fails to do the job it was designed for. However, a technique implicit in Meinong's investigation is more successful and can be adapted to resolve a similar paradox discovered by Romane Clark in a revised version of Meinong's Theory of Objects due (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  29.  16
    Further Evidence That the Effects of Repetition on Subjective Time Depend on Repetition Probability.William J. Skylark & Ana I. Gheorghiu - 2017 - Frontiers in Psychology 8.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  30. Computers Are Syntax All the Way Down: Reply to Bozşahin.William J. Rapaport - 2019 - Minds and Machines 29 (2):227-237.
    A response to a recent critique by Cem Bozşahin of the theory of syntactic semantics as it applies to Helen Keller, and some applications of the theory to the philosophy of computer science.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  31. Meinong, Alexius; I: Meinongian Semantics.William J. Rapaport - 1991 - In Hans Burkhardt & Barry Smith (eds.), Handbook of metaphysics and ontology. Munich: Philosophia Verlag. pp. 516-519.
    A brief introduction to Meinong, his theory of objects, and modern interpretations of it. Sections include: The Theory of Objects, Castañeda's Theory of Guises, Parsons,'s Theory of Nonexistent Objects, Rapaport's Theory of Meinongian Objects, Routley's Theory of Items.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  32. Religion and Morality.William J. Wainwright - 2006 - International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 59 (3):175-178.
  33.  8
    On behalf of the skolemite.William J. Thomas - 1971 - Analysis 31 (6):177-186.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  34. Reason and the Heart: A Prolegomenon to a Critique of Passional Reason.William J. Wainwright - 1995 - Religious Studies 32 (4):513-517.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  35. Assessing Ontological Arguments.William J. Wainwright - 2012 - European Journal for Philosophy of Religion 4 (2):19--39.
    Part I argues that ontological arguments, like other classical proofs of the existence of God, are parts of larger arguments in which they are embedded. These larger arguments include reasons supporting the proofs’ premises and responses to them, and to the proofs’ claims to validity and non-circularity, since, in the final analysis, our assessment of the proofs will express our best judgment of the cumulative force of all the considerations bearing on their overall adequacy. Part II illustrates these points by (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  36.  32
    Value and Existence.William J. Wainwright - 1981 - Philosophical Review 90 (2):318.
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  37.  78
    A non-probabilist principle of higher-order reasoning.William J. Talbott - 2016 - Synthese 193 (10).
    The author uses a series of examples to illustrate two versions of a new, nonprobabilist principle of epistemic rationality, the special and general versions of the metacognitive, expected relative frequency principle. These are used to explain the rationality of revisions to an agent’s degrees of confidence in propositions based on evidence of the reliability or unreliability of the cognitive processes responsible for them—especially reductions in confidence assignments to propositions antecedently regarded as certain—including certainty-reductions to instances of the law of excluded (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  38. On cogito propositions.William J. Rapaport - 1976 - Philosophical Studies 29 (1):63-68.
    I argue that George Nakhnikian's analysis of the logic of cogito propositions (roughly, Descartes's 'cogito' and 'sum') is incomplete. The incompleteness is rectified by showing that disjunctions of cogito propositions with contingent, non-cogito propositions satisfy conditions of incorrigibility, self-certifyingness, and pragmatic consistency; hence, they belong to the class of propositions with whose help a complete characterization of cogito propositions is made possible.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  39.  5
    I Can Wait 40 or 400 Years.William J. Starosta - 1993 - International Philosophical Quarterly 33 (2):163-172.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  10
    I Can Wait 40 or 400 Years.William J. Starosta & Anju G. Chaudhary - 1993 - International Philosophical Quarterly 33 (2):163-172.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41. An Apology for Apologetics: A Study in the Logic of Interreligious Dialogue by Paul J. Griffiths, and: Jesus Christ at the Encounter of World Religions by J. Dupuis.Gavin D'Costa - 1992 - The Thomist 56 (4):719-723.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:BOOK REVIEWS 719 An Apology for Apologetics: A Study in the Logic of lnterreligious Dialogue. By PAUL J. GRIFFITHS. New York: Orbis, 1991. ISBN: 0 88344 761 4. pp. 113. Jesus Christ at the Encounter of World Religions. By J. DUPUIS. New York: Orbis, 1991 (ET: Robert R. Barr, from French, 1989). ISBN: 0 88344 723 1. pp. 301. Griffiths presents a rigorous argument for the possibility of con· (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  2
    Contested Borders: Queer Politics and Cultural Translation in Contemporary Francophone Writing From the Maghreb.William J. Spurlin - 2018 - Rowman & Littlefield International.
    Contested Borders broadens understandings of dissident sexualities in Africa through focusing specifically on the Maghreb. It examines new representations of same-sex desire emerging in new francophone life writing, memoir, and literature from Algeria, Morocco, and Tunisia.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  20
    Two Theories of Mysticism.William J. Wainwright - 1975 - Modern Schoolman 52 (4):405-426.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  44.  12
    Reason and the Heart: A Prolegomenon to a Critique of Passional Reason.William J. Wainwright - 1995 - Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
    Between the opposing claims of reason and religious subjectivity may be a middle ground, William J. Wainwright argues. His book is a philosophical reflection on the role of emotion in guiding reason. There is evidence, he contends, that reason functions properly only when informed by a rightly disposed heart. The idea of passional reason, so rarely discussed today, once dominated religious reflection, and Wainwright pursues it through the writings of three of its past proponents: Jonathan Edwards, John Henry Newman, (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  45. God's Body.William J. Wainwright - 1987 - In Thomas V. Morris (ed.), The Concept of God. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 72-87.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  46.  26
    Integrating Instruction in Ethical Reasoning into Undergraduate Business Courses.William J. Wilhelm - 2008 - Journal of Business Ethics Education 5 (1):5-34.
    This article presents findings from a series of research studies designed to identify classroom teaching practices that can enhance moral reasoning of undergraduate students in business foundational courses. The research, conducted over five semesters at a Midwestern university, resulted in the development of teaching methods and materials that can, when properly sequenced and integrated into undergraduate business courses, increase levels of student moral reasoning as measured by the revised version of the Defining Issues Test (DIT-2). Findings in this research demonstrate (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  47.  4
    The Roles of the Ethics Consultant.William J. Winslade - 2011 - Journal of Clinical Ethics 22 (4):335-337.
    In this comment I discuss the role of an ethics case consultant in an institutional setting, in contrast to situations when an ethics consultant serves an individual client. In the former situation, I believe the case consultant should articulate ethical issues, options, and arguments, but not recommend a particular course of conduct. In the latter situation, the role of the ethics consultant can be defined and determined in negotiations with the client.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  48.  61
    The Portrait of Socrates in Plato's Symposium.William J. Prior - 2006 - In David Sedley (ed.), Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy Xxxi: Winter 2006. Oxford University Press. pp. 137-166.
    I argue that, when Alcibiades' encomium to Socrates is interpreted in light of Socrates' presentation of Diotima's speech, which immediately proceeds it, it shows Socrates to be at the top level of Diotima's "ladder of ascent" to Beauty. If Alcibiades is correct, Socrates' pretense of ignorance is an ironic sham. Socrates, as Plato's mystagogos, must have experiential knowledge of the Form of Beauty.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  49.  7
    Effects of a concurrent musical task on a unimanual skill.William J. Thomson & Susanne Clausnitzer - 1980 - Bulletin of the Psychonomic Society 16 (6):469-470.
  50.  15
    The Reliability of the Cognitive Mechanism: A Mechanist Account of Empirical Justification.William J. Talbott - 1990 - New York: Routledge.
    Originally published in 1990. Examining epistemic justification, truth and logic, this book works towards a holistic theory of knowledge. It discusses evidence, belief, reliability and many philosophical theories surrounding the nature of true knowledge. A thorough Preface updates the main work from when it was written in 1976 to include theories ascendant in the ‘80s.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
1 — 50 / 1000